January 2018

S M T W T F S
  123456
78910111213
14151617181920
21222324252627
28293031   

Page Summary

Style Credit

Expand Cut Tags

No cut tags
Sunday, April 8th, 2007 03:14 pm
Happy Easter, everybody! Today, I'm going to talk about two of my favourite logical fallacies. This post got a bit long, so I've split it into two: the second part, about Sliding Definition Ploy, is here.

My favourite, for the name if nothing else, is the No True Scotsman Fallacy1, which canonically goes like this:
Hamish: No true Scotsman puts sugar on his porridge.
Jock: But my cousin Angus MacAlasdair from Glen Coe puts sugar on his porridge.
[Beat.]
Hamish: No true Scotsman puts sugar on his porridge.
[We're assuming that Angus MacAlasdair's Scottish nationality is above reproach, apart from his unnatural and perverted breakfast habits.]

Hamish, unwilling to concede that his initial statement was wrong, has extended his definition of Scottishness to include "does not put sugar on his porridge". Angus, at least according to Hamish, has betrayed his nation and his ancestors by his choice of breakfast condiment, and thus does not deserve to be considered a true Scotsman. And yet an impartial observer, working to the generally-accepted definition of Scotsmanhood, would certainly say that Angus is a Scot, and a true one at that.

The NTS fallacy comes up a lot in arguments about evolution, where it commonly takes the form:
Fundie: A belief in evolution is incompatible with my Christian faith, so I must reject it.
Member of the reality-based community: Actually, no. Many, many Christians have no problem accepting evolution. In fact, evolution is accepted by nearly every major denomination of Christianity, and the denominations that accept it account for nearly all the Christians in the world.
Fundie: In that case, they can't really be Christians, can they?
MRBC: *headdesk*

NTS, used appropriately, can be a useful tool in mathematics: if you find a counterexample to some desirable theorem ("all Scotsmen suffer the symptoms of salt overconsumption", say), it may well be best to go back and refine your original definitions so that the counterexample disappears, then claim that what you really meant all along were the porridge-salting Scotsmen, you were just misled by the adjacent notion of "Scotsman". The trick is to do this explicitly, making it clear that the new definition ("porridge-salting Scotsman") is different from the old one ("Scotsman"), and excludes the pathological cases (Angus MacAlasdair). I did encounter the bad form in a conversation with a fellow mathematician the other day, though:
Colleague: Are there any categories without pushouts?
Me: Yeah, sure. In fact, it's quite unusual for a category to have pushouts.
Colleague: Can you give me an example of a category without pushouts?
[There follows a few minutes in which we try to find a "naturally-occurring" counterexample, which proves tricky to think about. Eventually, I give up and write down the first thing I'd thought of. In terms of our island metaphor, it's a shard of rock sticking out of the ocean at low tide, with a solitary seagull perched precariously on top of it, but it does provide a counterexample.]
Colleague: No, that's too categorical! A real category!
[You ask a category theorist, and then complain that the answer he gives you is too categorical? OK, whatever...]


By the way, porridge really is a lot tastier with salt on it. In fact, I'm eating some salted porridge now. Mmmm...

1 That's its name. Really!
Sunday, April 8th, 2007 07:44 pm (UTC)
I quoted your mathematical conversation to a mathy irc-channel, generating, among others, the following response that might be useful to you:
(@int-e) Syzygy-: so partial orders are not REAL categories?
(Anonymous)
Sunday, April 8th, 2007 07:45 pm (UTC)
*clutches her porridge with maple syrup*